Volume 1. No. 6 |
|
|
|
June 22, 2019 |
|
|
Abstract: Diagnostic
assessment tools are widely used instruments in research and clinical
practice to assess and evaluate autism symptoms for both children and
adults. These tools typically involve observing the child or adult under
assessment, and rating their behaviour for signs or
so-called symptoms of autism. In
order to examine how autism diagnosis is constructed, how diagnostic tools
are positioned, and how their trainings are delivered, we paid for four
places on a training course for a diagnostic tool. We asked the attendees (the
first four authors) to each produce a critical commentary about their
impressions of the training and the diagnostic tool itself. Their
commentaries are published here in full.
They have various disciplinary backgrounds: one is a social
scientist, one an ethicist, one a psychiatrist, and one a developmental
psychologist. The
commentaries are followed by a concluding section that summarises
the themes, commonalities, and differences between their accounts of the
training course. Authors differed as to whether the diagnostic tool is a
useful and necessary endeavour. Nevertheless, all
critiqued of the tool’s lack of transparency, recognizing context, emotion,
and differences in interpretation and power imbalances as playing an
unidentified role in the assessment process. Based on this project, we
recommend that training for raters for such tools should be accessible to a
wider group of people, and incorporate more explicit recognition of its own
limitations and commercialisation. |
Deconstructing Diagnosis: Four commentaries on
a diagnostic tool to assess individuals for autism spectrum disorders.
Introduction
Diagnostic
assessment tools such as the Autism Diagnostic Interview – Revised (ADI-R) and
the Autism Diagnostic Observation Schedule Second Edition (ADOS-2) (Lord et
al., 2012, 1994) are considered to be gold standard tools in research and
clinical practice to assess and evaluate autism symptoms for both children and
adults. These tools typically involve observing the child or adult under
assessment, and rating their behaviour for signs or
‘symptoms’ of autism. If the rater considers that the child or adult in
question displays frequent or severe symptoms of autism, they are given a high
score, and if this score is beyond a certain cut-off point, they are classified
as having autism. Such tools are routinely used in diagnostic assessment for
both children and adults in clinics, in combination with developmental history,
and other sources of information (Hayes et al. 2018). Researchers also use
diagnostic tools to identify cases in a given population who qualify as having
autism. However, non-clinicians, such as parents and autistic adults, rarely
have access to such tools and lack knowledge of how diagnostic decisions are
determined because raters require specialist training. In order to sit for a
training course in the UK for ADOS-2, for example, trainees must show evidence
they are a qualified clinician or practicing researcher. As such ‘who decides’
who has autism is limited to a highly qualified strata of society, perhaps
necessarily: a small group of highly trained clinicians and researchers.
Our
Wellcome Trust-funded project, called Exploring
Diagnosis (www.ex.ac.uk/exdx), and inspired by calls for a ‘sociology of
diagnosis’ (Jutel, 2011), studies how diagnostic
decisions about autism are made, by whom and for what purpose. In order to
examine how autism diagnosis is constructed, how diagnostic tools are
positioned and how training is delivered, in autumn 2017 we paid for four
places on a training course for ADOS-2, inviting four academics from different
disciplinary perspectives to attend. We asked them to produce a critical commentary
about their impressions of the training and the diagnostic tool itself (ADOS is
considered the gold standard for diagnostic observational assessment but we
could have chosen any similar diagnostic tool). The project was influenced by
other work that looks at how narratives are constructed by clinicians when they
use diagnostic tools to diagnose autism. For example, observing clinical
decision making following administration of a psychoeducational measure has
shown that clinicians use narrative to separate out autism as a diagnosis (Turowetz, 2015). We were also influenced by research
showing how diagnostic tests operate to shape the environments both in terms of
the interaction between test ‘subject’ and clinician, and in terms of the
setting and atmosphere in which the test is conducted (Maynard and Turowetz, 2017). Such work suggests the nature of the
diagnostic test itself may influence the diagnostic outcome. In addition, Hayes
and colleagues (2018) have shown that diagnostic guidelines encourage clinicians
making diagnostic decisions to consider many social and contextual factors
unrelated to whether a child or adult displays symptoms of autism as measured
by such tools. We wondered whether the diagnostic tools themselves might
promote the construction of diagnostic narratives (and if so, how). This is
important because when diagnostic decisions are made by multidisciplinary
teams, the ‘symptoms of autism’ that a child or adults displays (generally
measured with ADOS or another similar diagnostic tool) are often read as an
objective measure of autism.
A
second reason for embarking on this small project was to counter the lack of
transparency about how diagnostic ratings are obtained in clinical practice. Having said that, of the four commentators who sat the course, only
one was a practicing clinician. The four were selected because each has,
for different reasons and in different ways and contexts, expressed a critical
interest in the medicalisation of autism. These four
academic authors are also members of the autism community (defined as autistic
people, their families, and professionals who work with them by Kenny et al.,
2016). Two of the commentators are autistic activists,
two were parents of children identified as being on the autism spectrum, and
one a clinician noted for his critical perspective. All have been vocal
campaigners or commentators, engaging with social and scientific institutions
to both promote or resist the framing of autism as pathological, so they have
all been actively involved in processes of medicalisation
and/or de-medicalisation (Jenkins and Short,
2017). Given that the commentators were
invited because of their distinctive history in relation to autism, we do not
claim the views they recorded are representative of any particular group (all
parents, for example). As diagnostic training is limited to a select band, we
were keen to invite people with an alternative perspective who were likely to
question whether the diagnostic tool really can be considered an objective measure
of autism. That being said, it is important to note, as one of the reviewers
put it, these commentaries are ‘no more objective than the instrument they are
examining’. The authors are all known
for positions allowing that autism is both a social construct and an actual
neurodevelopmental difference, and we acknowledge that their views and the
knowledges about autism are situated in their considerable combined experience
(Haraway, 1988).
The
following accounts, then, are personal reflections of the commentators on the
training process for ADOS and the tool itself, written by these authors soon
after they sat in on the ADOS training course. The critical commentaries are
published here in full. The authors were asked to observe and make notes,
especially in light of the language of the course and power relations
diagnostic assessment entails. The
training took place over several days, was intensive by design, and covered an
introduction to the course and four separate modules of the diagnostic tool
differentiated by children and (young) adults’ age and level of expressive
language. The training incorporated watching filmed clips and grading children
according to the set criteria, and finally a review of how to apply the tool in
practice. These four authors independently wrote their own reflective
commentaries without reference to, nor any consultation with, each other. This
was so that we captured their individual and disciplinary perspectives, to
express only their own diverse views. The accounts that follow show how
diagnostic assessment tools are used to quantify individuals’ behaviour and include arguments about how this may serve to
both hinder and help their development. The accounts are followed by a
concluding section that summarises the themes,
commonalities and differences between these accounts.
1. A window on the Autism Industry
Sami
Timimi is a consultant child and Adolescent
Psychiatrist.
In
May 2017 I attended, along with 13 other participants, training in the use of a
diagnostic scale for autism. The cost per delegate for this course is over
£500. The full extended training takes 4-5 days and costs over £1000. The
training is advertised as being an approved course after successful completion
of which you are ‘licenced’ to administer on patients
the assessment. However, in order to administer the assessment you must also
purchase an administration pack, which contains 50 assessment booklets (as well
as other materials you might need) and costs nearly £2000. At the start of the
course each participant also received a booklet advertising numerous other
courses and assessment packs available for purchase. Any doubt that this is not
a commercial ‘product’, and part of a wider money making industry were lessened
when the course facilitator, in response to a question on what module you could
use with adults who have little language or use typing for communication,
answered that such a module had not been developed as it was “not commercially
viable”.
I
attended this course in the peculiar position of being both student and
researcher; there to observe, document, and potentially deconstruct the
assessment. As a consultant child and adolescent psychiatrist I frequently
encounter young people who have been diagnosed with an Autism Spectrum Disorder
(ASD) and the tool we were taught remains the most frequently used assessment
‘tool’ for establishing a diagnosis. I am aware that as an author who has
written sceptically about the validity of ASD as a
diagnostic concept, I would not be able to view the content of the course
through a value neutral prism. Therefore, as the rest of this article
represents my views of the assumptions, beliefs, and practices, related to the
course and the tool, it will reflect my particular bias.
The
tool is advertised as being a “semi-structured standardised
measure of communication and social deficits and play associated with ASD“
(note the language of ‘standardised’, ‘measure’,
‘deficits’ depicting an empirically valid and quantifiable approach to
identifying a medical problem). It is described as incorporating a series of
“standard activities, providing opportunities to observe behaviours
directly relevant to diagnosis of ASD at different developmental levels and chronological
ages”.
Before
presenting my reflections, it’s worth remembering the overall context, which
reflects several levels of assumptions. This includes that ASD exists as a
discrete, natural ‘thing’, that this autism ‘thing’ can be identified and quantified,
that identification and measurement can be done validly and reliable through
specific assessment tools, that the training was in use of one such tool, that
the items in it encompass and identify the ‘symptoms’ that make up ASD, that it
has good psychometrics to enable sensitivity and specificity, and that it is
reliable and can be ‘standardised’. Each assumptive
level is open to question. If any of these assumptions are unwarranted, then
the validity of the diagnostic tool is also open to question.
The training
The
language used betrays deep assumptions that were implicit during the course.
There was no acknowledgement that these assessments take place in a particular
context (e.g. a medical clinic following concerns expressed by someone about a child)
or that the behaviour of the examiner could have an
impact on how the patient subsequently behaved. The assumption was that the
context and examiner side of the relational dynamic in the assessment room are
non-significant, so that what emerges during the assessment is purely the
result of the interiority of the patient. Throughout the two days the language
used betrayed this assumptive framework. For example, the tool can be ‘standardised’ and made ‘objective’, features that achieve a
rating are ‘symptoms’, that the job of a ‘good assessor’ will be to ‘look for
symptoms’. The language is one of objectification, words such as ‘objective’,
‘abnormal’, ‘standardised’, ‘measurement’, ‘symptoms’, ‘severe’ and so
on, regularly appeared.
The
quasi-autistic rigidity of seeing only ‘real’ internal qualities in the
patients was a recurrent theme. Most of the questions I asked during the course
stemmed from genuine puzzlement as to how certain patient behaviours
in the videos, the course facilitator ascribed as solely the consequence of
symptoms in the patient. The reaction of the facilitator to my questions were
defensive, insisting that what was being observed could only be understood as
being the manifestations of ASD spilling out into the session. The context and
assessment process, they argued, were standardised,
allowing for objective ratings to be made that were shaped by the impulses of
the patient. Thus, as the facilitator guided us through the scoring, they kept
referring to the ‘fact’ that this or that symptom occurred. Non-pathologising interpretations were not tolerated. We were
all being trained to become examiners with a keen eye for noticing every
minutiae of the not ‘normal’ about the patient.
There
was a mechanistic view of how social interaction occurs and can be manipulated.
The scenarios/tasks are set up as if the examiner, their actions, and the
environment, exist as controllable variables with what emerges as irrefutably
demonstrating the patients’ social abnormalities. In one clinical example, the
course facilitator, discussing a previous patient’s interactions with his
mother, demonstrated this one sided view. In this example the mother told this
child, “Why do you never look at me?” The child then started to look at her.
The mother now complained, “Why do you stare at me?” The confused boy now
decided maybe he should learn to look at her and then away from her. His mother
now complained, “Why do you move your eyes from one place to another?”
According to this story, the boy eventually developed a complex formula for how
long to look at her and away from her. In recounting this tale the facilitator
made no comment about this mother’s role in this developing relational
discomfort – it was all the result of this kid’s (at the time undiagnosed) ASD.
The symptoms and ratings
No
allowance is made for the gender or cultural relevance of the
activities/questions. The illusion of objectivity starts dissolving when you
see the wording of what you are being asked to rate. For example, for rating
“Stereotyped/idiosyncratic use of words or phrases” a mark of 2 (indicating
high degree of abnormality) is given if “often uses stereotyped utterances or
odd words or phrases, with some other language”. A mark of 1 (indicating some
level of abnormality) is “Use of words or phrases tends to be more repetitive
than that of most individuals at the same level of expressive language, but not
obviously odd”. For, “Quality of social overtures”, 1 is “Slightly unusual
quality of some social overtures. Overtures may be restricted to personal
demands or related to the child’s own interests, but with some attempt to
involve the assessor”, 2 is “Significant minority (or more) of inappropriate
overtures; many overtures lack integration into context and/or social quality”.
Note that words like ‘often’, ‘unusual’, ‘quality’, ‘some’, ‘odd’ and so on,
all require an examiner to interpret – they do not lend themselves to
establishing objective facts.
Reliance
on the interpretive bias of the examiner was regularly revealed. For example in
one video assessment we observed I saw the child regularly smiling, but the
facilitator said this was not smiling but ‘smirking’. Furthermore, it is
difficult to understand why that should be considered a medical ‘symptom’.
Other behaviours rated included: ‘unusual’ use of words; quality of child’s
attempt to initiate interaction; whether patient requests things from the
examiner; not spontaneously giving toys or other objects to examiner; not
showing toys or other objects (e.g. by holding them up) to the examiner; lack
of flexible, creative use of objects (e.g. a doll) in a representational
manner; unusual sensory interests; and so on, are all open to interpretive
variation. All the ratings are of this nature. They bring up questions of where
notions of appropriate/inappropriate, normal/abnormal, healthy/symptomatic etc.
are derived from and that lead to the categorical diagnostic decisions.
My
genuine interpretations using the scoring systems were quite different to that
of what the facilitator explained were the ‘objective’ scores, particularly for
the two younger patients in the videos for Modules 1 and 2. In fact when Module
1 video was shown, I was convinced that this was being shown to illustrate an
assessment of a ‘normal’ child to show us the contrast.
Watching the videos of assessments
I
found the videos of Module 1 and 2 assessments painful to watch. The examiner
moves quickly from one activity to another, giving each activity a few minutes.
In these modules the children were around 3 and 5 years old. The
‘objectification’ of their behaviours spoke to me
more about power and a privileged construction of ‘truth’ than the discovery of
anything intrinsic to the child. Both children seemed to me to become
uncomfortable and in different ways uncooperative (yet still forced to comply),
due to, at least in part, the context and unusual behaviour
of the examiner. We could only comment on and then code the patient’s behaviour, but were not allowed to interpret the patient’s
possible affect or relational/contextual nature of interaction, which looked
quite distressing for the young patients at times. It seemed to me that this
‘test’ of social communication was done through setting up a deliberately
provocative environment and expecting these young patients to acquiesce
unconditionally to the examiner’s demands.
Thus,
to me, these looked more like tests of social conformity to a bossy adult’s
constantly shifting demands. In one video, early in the session, after the
examiner removes the toys the patient was playing with, the patient stands with
his back to the examiner and says “You’re not my friend”. The rest of the
session plays out a complex interaction, part at times hilarious rebellion by
the young patient, part engagement, part distressing to watch pressurising and detachment by the examiner. To me the
peculiarly detached, at times repetitive questioning, at times exaggerated
unnatural smiling and high-pitched squeaky childish voice of the examiner,
appeared more unusual than that of the reaction of the child. However, using
the tool this child had ASD and was apparently the ‘abnormal’ of the two
actors.
Conclusion
This
tool is a diagnostic trap. An invented (socially constructed
if you prefer that language) assessment, for an invented set of symptoms that
is subjective and lacks insight into role of context and the inter-subjective
nature of relationships. It attempts to identify relational ‘deficit’
whilst demonstrating the instrument’s own lack of awareness about the nature of
relationships. It relentlessly seeks to uncover evidence of ‘abnormalities’ and
creates a context where the examiner can readily find it. It is a system that
catches many in its net, from young kids who won’t do as the examiner instructs
and in the way the examiner believes they should, to older ones who have an
interesting turn of phrase. It is infected with the Western colonial arrogance
where the creators, sellers, and now the many examiners who carry out these
assessments, believe that they ‘know’ how the universal, culture, gender,
sexuality neutral person should and shouldn’t function. They shamelessly
promote and sell this around the world subjecting ever more children and adults
to its perverse normalization/pathologisation
agenda.
2. The tool that could not be used (by
autistic people)
Damian
Milton is a social scientist, autistic and the parent of an autistic child.
I
approached this project with a strong sense of trepidation, and for many
reasons I was indeed right to feel such apprehension. Not only was the training
that I attended an intense programme with limited
breaks, but the language utilised (particularly in
the materials) was difficult to engage with without having an emotional
reaction to it. This I found particularly problematic for a number of items utilised for assessing adolescents. Having said this, I
would like to thank the individual that delivered the training for their
efforts, and for what was no doubt a difficult group to work with.
Throughout
the training a pathologised deficit model of autism
was utilised, framed as a developmental disorder that
one could establish through the accurate recording of atypical behaviours across a number of specified domains. Potential
strengths of being autistic were absent from the discourse. This ontology was
presented as factual, evidence-based and validated. The discourse produced
regarding autistic personhood is therefore that of a disordered
‘biopsychosocial other’. This included for example recording autistic behaviour as “mechanical” and thus reifying the much
critiqued machine-like metaphor often used to describe autistic people (Milton,
2014). Such a framing is reminiscent of Foucault’s (Foucault, 1973) concept of
the ‘medical gaze’, but rather than suggesting the separation of mind and body
in a dualistic fashion, the mind is reduced to body and behavioural
contingencies deemed either normal or abnormal, irrespective of cultural
influences.
“What
we want to see is requesting behaviour, eye contact
and other communicative behaviour” (trainer).
This
quote indicates that the more abnormal, idiosyncratic, absent, overactive
etcetera, a behaviour is seen to be, the more likely
it will record a score. Of course, in some measurements, these are well defined,
in others however, they are far less so, and are far more dependent upon the
tacit intuitions of the professional administrating the test.
In
order to be deemed competent enough to administer the test, a professional
would need to score over 80% reliability with other practitioners. In this
sense, reliability is built on a consensus of how to administer and interpret
the behaviours of others. Upon completing the
practice examples of coding on the training course, it became apparent that I
was perhaps ‘top of the class’ in spotting anything to do with ‘sensory’
related activity, but consistently rated the people in the film clips as having
more social insight and reciprocal interaction than I was ‘meant to’. It would
be a very interesting test to see if autistic people reliably perceived such
social interactions in this way. Of course, a pathologised
account of such interpretations might suggest that an autistic person lacks the
social insight and social skills to see them lacking in others, or one would
have a lower personal perceptual threshold due to one’s own difficulties in
this area. Or, one might see these instances as a mismatch of salience within
social contexts, differences in expressive language, or disposition, more akin
to the ‘double empathy problem’ that I have previously discussed (Milton, 2014;
Wittemeyer, et al., 2012), referring to the mutual
breakdown in reciprocity often found in interactions between autistic and
non-autistic people, and the wider power dynamics this is situated within.
There
was great emphasis throughout the training placed on it being seen as standardised, reliable, and objective. The materials were
presented as the ‘gold standard’ of diagnostic tools, based on “international
consensus”. However, a number of aspects of the programme
could bring this into question. The trainer even suggested at one point that
two of the items within the schedule were not objective but subjective and
intuitive. One is meant to make brief notes whilst administering the test
items, film recording was seen as optional, and the order of the tasks
non-compulsory. It was said at one point that parents should not be present,
yet this was contradicted by the practice experience of one of the trainees who
attended the course. Taking such aspects of data collection into account, one
could question both the reliability and standardised
nature of the tool.
The
algorithm used to calculate the overall score an individual receives is clear,
but it is not exactly clear as to how each item and weighting was arrived at,
nor thresholds for indicating what was described by the trainer as the
‘severity of symptomology’. The overall number of items used to define the
threshold for autism contained nearly twice as many items for ‘social
interaction’ compared to either ‘language and comprehension’ or ‘restricted
interests and behaviours’. Such a framing of autism
suggests a deficit model based on the model of a ‘triad of impairments’, with
the strongest weighting being on deficits in perceived ‘theory of mind’. Such a
framing is contested however by a number of autistic scholars (Chown, 2014;
Lawson, 2010; Milton, 2012; Murray et al., 2005; Wittemeyer,
et al., 2012) as well as research studies (Gernsbacher et al., 2017; Sasson et al., 2017; Sheppard et al., 2016) that suggest
‘theory of mind’ is dispositional and contextual in its performance.
Other
than a brief mention regarding their being available an array of “treatment
packages”, the importance of diagnosis and intervention did not enter into
discussions to a great extent. The focus instead was directed toward accurate
assessment and the tool’s reliability. The importance of diagnosis and what
resultant ‘treatment’ might look like was somewhat implied however,
particularly when one takes into account the theoretical and discursive framing
of how autism was being accounted for in the training documents. This brief
mention did however frame autism within a medical model and also suggested how
such treatment was commercialised into ‘packages’.
“Anything
the child does, we are so happy!” (trainer).
The
more an individual performed in a typical fashion, the ‘better’ it was deemed
for a person, perhaps by implication suggesting that non-autistic people are
‘better’ people? Such a discursive framing helps to fuel the use of remedial
interventions (whether evidence-based or not), rather than looking at the
multiple nuanced reasons why these observed behaviours
may be occurring. None of the items rated in the scale on their own would
indicate a diagnosis of autism, yet an overall high score on a number of
factors would. It would be possible to meet the threshold showing very
different presentations of autism, yet this is always defined in relation to
the typically developing child, becoming a collective umbrella term for developmental
trajectories of ‘othered’ humans.
Such
othering led to phenomena such as echolalia being described as not meaningful.
Autistic ways of being are described as “compensatory strategies”. Interests
are described as “obsessions”, “fixated” and abnormal for not being able to
“shift flexibly around the interests and behaviour of
the administrator”, whilst the reverse is seen as unproblematic. The use of eye
contact in conjunction with other behaviours
described as “appropriate”, not to mention the discourse of “temper tantrums”
or “empathy” in relation to cartoon characters. Behaviours
recorded are done so from the perspective of a non-autistic pathological model,
and therefore when “little sense of reciprocity” is recorded by the
professional, the breakdown in mutual comprehension is seen as the fault of
only the autistic person’s behavioural ‘deficits’.
Girls on the spectrum were presented by the trainer, as to often have more
‘typical interests’, or interests in social science subjects “sparked by their
underlying difficulties”, seemingly missing that I had announced that I was an
autistic social scientist myself at the beginning of the training, and if I am
not mistaken present as male.
Throughout
the process, it was patently obvious that the amount of autistic input into the
design of the tool was next to zero. Why else would “empathising
comments from the administrator” be encouraged one might ask (such fakery if
seen as such may not be taken kindly), or test administrators being required to
be “larger than life” according to the training materials? Given that autistic
people (as defined by the scale criteria) are more likely to have sensory
sensitivities, perhaps reducing such mannerisms might be beneficial? Also,
being clear and honest may be better than acting ‘empathetic’ to a person one
has just met and is putting covertly through a medicalised
behavioural assessment schedule? An important part of
applying the various activities contained in the schedule highlighted in the
training was the use of what were called ‘social presses’. This term applied to
prompting social activities through providing cues which were thought to
determine in advance a likely behavioural response in
terms of a child’s profile in relation to stages of development. This would
involve ‘scaffolding’ social interaction to see if a child / young person
reacts as expected and with what level of support. The positionality of the
professional administrating the tool is firmly framed however, as that of a
non-autistic person. Perceptions of interaction, sensory differences, interests
and behaviours all need to be coded in terms of
deviation from the ‘typical’ norm. Therefore, the power relations presented by
the tool places the clinician firmly at the centre.
In
the definition of autism presented, autistic people would lack the social
insight and intuitions needed to adequately assess it in others. It is
certainly true, that my honest assessments would probably not reach the
reliability standards required for someone to be seen as a competent user of
the test materials (despite perhaps a more accurate assessment of cognitive and
sensory differences). Within such a discursive framing, it would be impossible
for an autistic person to be trained to be fully ‘reliable’ in administrating the
test, leaving clinicians with the power not only to define “autism” to some
extent, but being the gatekeepers of who can access the diagnostic category.
Therefore, the positionality and theoretical framing of the assessment helps to
create an intensely wide power divide with all the social and personal
consequences that dynamic could lead to.
The
training suggested that those administrating the test should always be “keeping
the parent in mind” and their emotional reactions to the processes being undertaken.
Little emphasis however was placed on the wellbeing of the ‘child’ under
observation. An adult under such observation would likely feel patronised, if not dehumanised.
One has to question the ethics of informed consent for the individuals and
families who undergo such assessments. Professionals utilising
the tool are advised not to give out the quantitative data to those under
examination, thus controlling the systems that identify people as autistic or
not. I would argue that such tools creates a contrived social situation
embroiled in (yet often disguised) unequal power relations and reify a conceptualisation of autism which directly leads to the
disempowerment of autistic voices.
Lastly,
I would just like to mention the more than present ‘elephant in the room’ which
stalked the training throughout, and that was the idealisation
and reification of developmental ‘normalcy’. Perhaps my colleague on the
training Sami Timimi would consider working with me
on a follow-up to his previous text on the ‘myth of autism’ (Timimi et al., 2011): ‘The myth of normal’?
3. Picture the scene
Virginia
Bovell is an ethicist and parent activist
I
am one of a group people who are being trained to use a diagnostic tool for
autism. We are watching a filmed
interaction between a diagnostician and a small boy.
The
boy is doing things with a laminated picture that you wouldn’t expect of a
typically-developing child. He is
placing it on his head, then he lifts it and waves it
around. He seems to be experimenting
with how it feels and how it looks at different angles as it moves through
light and air. And he seems to be
fascinated and extremely pleased with what he is doing.
My
neighbour, a fellow trainee, and I start to
laugh. We laugh with recognition and
delight in the fun the boy is having. He
is not reliant on approval from the diagnostician, and we appreciate his
exuberance and his ability to see things differently.
It
takes a while for me to notice the atmosphere in the room. It seems no one else is laughing.
Later,
I reflect on what happened.
The
first thing to point out is that the two of us who laughed both have autistic
children. Was it this that helped us to
celebrate some charming and commendable qualities in this boy’s behaviour, rather than rue them and pathologise
them? Possibly. Yet our response doesn’t just say something
about us as parents - it says something about the nature of autism itself,
which is described by many as integral to someone’s whole person, rather than
being just a part (Grandin, 2006; Sinclair, 2012).
For
example, if we had been watching most scenes in which a child was being
assessed to identify a potential disability – visual impairment say – it would
be cruel to laugh. If she was bumping
into objects that she couldn’t see, then laughter would denote the most
sadistic kind of slapstick humour. Indeed, I wonder if the others were thinking
something similar about us, as my colleague and I laughed with this little boy,
whose diagnosis of autism would shortly be confirmed. Did they see in us some kind of callous
indifference at best, or taunting insensitivity at worst?
“I
was laughing with empathy”, my colleague says to me later. In the classic phrase, we weren’t laughing at
him, we were laughing with him. We were
delighting in his single-mindedness, lack of conformity, freedom of spirit.
So
what does this say about autism?
I
am reminded of the phrase “the duality of autism and giftedness” (Walsh,
2010). This is the suggestion that the
advantages and disadvantages in autism are two sides of the same coin, that
there are real strengths alongside the deficits upon which diagnosis
fixates. Yes, our boy may not be
displaying much ability for social interaction, but on the other hand he may
well be displaying enhanced perceptual awareness of the sight and sound and
feel of the object he is manipulating (Mottron et
al., 2006).
I
am also reminded of Michelle Dawson’s account of a similar scenario. In a presentation in 2012 (Dawson, 2012),
she spoke about how she, and she alone among a large audience, took pleasure in
observing a child so fascinated and absorbed in his object of interest that he
didn’t pause to interact with the human being beside him. Dawson likened the audience’s emotional
response to a paragraph of emojis: row upon row of sad faces, interrupted with a
lone smiley face. The smiley face was
Dawson’s. Resolutely at odds with the
others, she was alone in seeing something positive and natural in the child’s behaviour, in contrast to the others who were hung up on
the absence of social interaction.
But
if we only did things that other humans required of us, what kind of society
would we be living in? There is
evidence that autistic people may be less susceptible to social pressure, and
therefore able to make more stable moral and perceptual judgments, (Cage et
al., 2013; Izuma et al., 2011). Others (for example Wendy Lawson (Lawson,
2010, 2008)) cite the creative potential that comes with independent
perception.
So
at this point my instinct is to regard the diagnostic process as one that
sidelines qualities of real ability and strength. By perseverating on reduced
levels of social interaction, we seem only to be looking at what he’s not
doing, rather than where he excels.
A
couple of us try to point this out:
“Surely”
I say to the trainer “ he simply wasn’t as interested
in the person as he was in what he was doing”.
And this, I suggest, chimes with the monotropism
theory of autism (Murray et al., 2005) whereby the distinct cognitive style of
autistic people relates chiefly to a paramount focus on interests, and this
should not be devalued or ignored.
But
here comes the reality check. The
trainer tells us about the boy’s history, in the context of his social and
institutional surroundings.
Imagine
the world this boy inhabits, with its social pressures and rules, the
constraints of school and the demands of the wider environment. Imagine the future that lies ahead of him. If this young chap is so single-mindedly
averse to prompts and guidance from others - if he remains impervious to the
social world of the NT majority and unaware of how to make his way in it - how
will he stay safe, have his needs met, thrive?
If he struggles to express himself and be understood, to the point of
exclusion at best, and abuse and victimization at worst, what will become of
him?
I
understand the trainer’s point of view.
But still it feels unfair to hone in on this boy’s deficits, given that
his contribution is only part of what might lead to such potential
difficulties. As Milton (Milton, 2012)
has described it, there is a double empathy problem in operation, a mutual
incomprehension. Or,
as another colleague has put it, “Robinson Crusoe couldn’t have been autistic until
he found Man Friday” (Starr, 2009).
This speaks to the primary emphasis on social interaction that the
diagnosis of autism requires. In this
sense, autism is not only – or perhaps at all - an individual problem. It is all about the individual within a
wider social environment. As many
autistic writers and their NT sympathisers have
written, people around the autistic person should also learn to adapt. We must – as it were - meet an autistic
person halfway, since the problem is not so much within him or her, as it is
within the mismatch between him/her and the wider world. “Empathy is not a one-way street” (Chown,
2013).
Given
this focus on autism as a phenomenon requiring two or more people, is the
individual-focused nature of the current diagnostic process inherently
misconceived? How do you get a fixed measure of something that is by definition
inter-relational?
Paradoxically
perhaps, I begin to recognise that it is precisely
because autism is about the relationship between an individual and their
(social) environment that obtaining a diagnosis might help the boy. Without it, will there be any attempt to
recognize a need for others to adjust their approach to him? Will he be viewed merely as willfully
uncooperative and hence condemned to exclusion without support? What if, in a world dominated by NTs, his
contrasting interests and the need for both him and others to adjust how they
try to interact, goes by un-signposted and hence un-recognised??
And
what about this boy’s future sense of his own
self? What if the opportunity to find
other people with similar dispositions is missed? This could happen, without the label that
helps people find like-minded others. I
am thinking here of the many first-person accounts from people who have acquired
a diagnosis after years in the wilderness; the relief in finding they are not
alone but are in fact part of a community with a shared sense of identity
(Chapman, 2016; Dekker, 2016).
This
search for others with shared experiences applies not just for the individuals
themselves, but for their families.
When a diagnosis comes, parents can look for and then find each other,
to get help and information about how to build a case for the reasonable
adjustments their child may need. With
knowledge of the specific domains of challenge facing their children, parents
can push for improved services, until such a time – if it ever does come - that
their children are able to self-advocate.
In other words, diagnosis can build ‘solidarity’ (Prainsack
and Buyx, 2011).
Some
might argue against this idea of solidarity, pointing instead to the divisions
in the autism community. With its
several dimensions, and its sometimes startlingly varying manifestations, we
may of course be talking about autisms plural, rather than the singular
monolithic entity that continues to elude natural and social scientists alike (Happé and Ronald, 2008; Müller and Amaral,
2017; Verhoeff, 2012). This had led (Chapman, 2017) to offer an
analogy between autism and the feminist movement with regard to intersectional
theory and differences: the priorities of learning disabled autistics and those
with co-occurring conditions may not always be congruent with those of able,
articulate autistics, just as the experiences of black women and white women
within the feminist movement will not always be the same.
I
believe there will be much more written about this in the coming years, but in
the meantime, I still feel there is an important utility in the umbrella
category of autism spectrum disorder.
It crucially signposts the potential need for supports – even if the
nature of these supports will vary according to individuals and contexts. If you start to chip away at diagnosis, you
take away services - a point made very clearly by the furore
surrounding a London service proposal to change the criteria (see (Dreaper, 2017).
Acquiring
a passport to entitlements needs to done on a fair, transparent and
non-arbitrary basis, and criteria that meet some
semblance of objectivity are necessary also in the area of intervention
studies. We all want to be assured that society is investing in effective
support systems, not wasteful and harmful ones (see for example (Fleming et
al., 2016). So, notwithstanding the many
challenges, I have supported the call for more intervention research. We need to be able to trust the measures that
have been used in such studies, such as the PACT research, which was widely
commended for its adherence to good scientific standards (Mottron,
2017). But as a lay person reading about PACT, I was none the wiser about the
precise nature of the tool used to measure the outcomes. And that is precisely why I welcomed the
opportunity to learn about the diagnostic tool….
…
which brings me back to the opening scenario in this
article. Here I am, on this course,
amongst a group of people who are learning what goes on in the diagnostic
process and how to administer the tool.
I like and trust my fellow trainees’ concern for their client group, and
the trainer is clearly steeped not just in diagnostic protocols but in the
real-life challenges facing her subjects, for whom she feels great
affection. Everyone here is approaching
the task in good faith. Setting aside
the controversy over whether people can self-diagnose, it seems obvious that
self-identification of autism is never going to be a viable or realistic way
forward for many - young children for example, or adults with learning
disabilities. So I do see the merit in
our shared endeavour.
Still,
I feel ambivalent. I’m uneasy about the
medical dominance in the use of such tools with regard to autism. My involvement as a ‘lay’ person testifies
to the fact that you don’t need to be employed in professions allied to
medicine, to learn how to use the tools.
And it is disconcerting that the diagnostic materials are
copyrighted. People get a diagnosis that
can change their lives, but accessing the criteria by which they are diagnosed
is hidden behind a paywall. Permission
to diagnose and assess becomes an adjunct of a wider medical/industrial system
in which only certain people have power, and in which some people profit, while
the people who go off and live their lives post-diagnosis seem relatively
passive and powerless in the process.
And
I am concerned about the extent to which diagnosis is imprecise, despite the
scoring systems and algorithms and use of identical testing materials. During our training it becomes apparent that
there is room for considerable disagreement and several interpretations of the
same phenomena. This worries me, given
that the implications are huge – where a divergence of one or two points might
make the difference between diagnosis and non-diagnosis. Talking to my fellow trainees, it becomes
clear that they share this concern. How
reliable are they going to be during the months/years in which they are still
relative novices, and does this concern apply also to the testers in the
intervention trials?
So
much remains elusive, but perhaps this is inevitable.
If there is still no shared understanding of a definitive autistic essence, how
can there be a definitive diagnostic tool?
It will no doubt continue to change with successive incarnations of the
international classification systems, and with greater identification of
subgroups.
To
meet their critics, the committees who decide on the criteria and on the
resultant diagnostic tools will need to seek out the contribution of autistic
people and those who live with them.
They will need to give greater recognition of the positive features of
autism and the positive qualities that autistic people have, and the whole
process should come out from behind the wall of professional and commercial
exclusivity.
I
believe we need to keep discussing these issues, across ‘lay’ and
‘professional’ stakeholder groups, and I hope this series of articles might
contribute helpfully to the discourse.
4. Diagnosing the diagnosis of
autism: systematic pathologisation or a key to
understanding?
Steven
K. Kapp is a developmental psychologist & autistic activist.
A
clinical training of an interaction-based assessment tool illuminated autism’s
construction as a disorder mostly of social communication diagnosed mainly
according to the observations of non-autistic people. My experience with the
training highlighted that while standardised behavioural assessments may pathologise
autism, overlook the individual’s perspective, and occur in an artificial
context, instruction on how to interpret observable actions may provide at
least some consistency that might further access to services. It also might
serve as a basis for research on which supports help which individuals, as we
know little about who benefits from an autism diagnosis. While the facilitator
shared predetermined scores for behaviours under the
guise of a ‘discussion’ to achieve ‘consensus’, a training for research
reliability would have had even less room for interpretation, which at least
provides a stable foundation upon which to investigate the validity.
One
could readily focus a critique on the commercialisation
of the autism field into an industry. Indeed, the training began by passing
around leaflets or catalogues to other courses and assessment materials by the
psychometric product corporation that provided our meeting space and objects
from pens to graph paper marked with their logo. It ended with an e-mail from
the company to receive a 5 percent discount on any products for the assessment
or another related training course upon completion of a post-training coding
assignment. This completion would also provide a certification for participants
to use (any module of) the tool in clinical practice despite only attending two
days of a group training that struggled to make time for the four age- and
language-based modules across the autism spectrum and even less for individual
attention (but plenty of opportunity to observe sanctioned behaviours
like pressing knuckles against the side of the face while looking away, which a
trainee might mark down as socially inappropriate listening if observed in an
autistic client).
Moreover,
the scale suffers from an administration in an artificial context that may not
have ecological validity. Unfamiliar adults administer it, which may
disadvantage autistic people uncomfortable with strangers but who may display
relatively typical markers of sociality among loved ones such as parents
(Feldman et al., 2014; Parma et al., 2013), and yet the number of caregivers
who attend the testing sessions does not affect the coding.
Alternatively,
this format may advantage autistic children and adolescents who may relate
relatively well to adults – or even perceive higher quality of life in their
relationships with authority figures like parents and teachers than typically
developing youth (Cottenceau et al., 2012). The
experience of testing under explicit instructions may disadvantage autistic
people who have difficulty with executing actions on command due to movement
(dyspraxia) and executive functioning challenges (Mostofsky
and Ewen, 2011). While atypically high automatic
imitation (in behaviour – echopraxia
– or words – echolalia) associates with higher degrees of autism (Bird et al.,
2007; Sowden et al., 2016; Spengler et al., 2010), the training may encourage
codes that dismiss the mimicry as not ‘meaningful’ or ‘spontaneous’.
Participation may not reflect full consent, and even attempts to build rapport
by enthusiastic and high-pitched clinicians (which the facilitator praised) may
backfire, as ‘babytalk’ (child-directed speech) often
does not benefit the communication of autistic children as it may for their
typically developing counterparts (Solomon, 2011) – possibly because it may
exacerbate to focus on the phonology (sound) of words at the expense of
semantics (meaning) (Norbury et al., 2010). Thus the
tool suffers from the limitations of interaction and perception by clinicians
who may struggle to interpret autistic people’s behaviour,
yet the training is to interpret particular behaviours
in particular ways (especially taught and enforced for research reliability),
which at least promotes consistency.
Eyeing Autism: Optical Illusion or a
Matter of Perspective?
The facilitator explained that coders too
often disagree on subtle or slight observed atypicalities
in eye contact, so they now receive training to only mark them when quite clear,
reflecting difficulties in measurement despite its emphasis in various autism
assessments. Coders also must penalise an individual
even when they seem merely ‘shy’ and disregard any eye contact made with a
caregiver or loved one in the room. Culturally competent coders may recognise that children in non-Western cultures, as well as
atypically developing children in the U.K. (such as autistic and blind
children), may not rely on gaze for reciprocal social interaction (Akhtar and
Gernsbacher, 2008). Even crèche (day care) staff in South Africa who
self-perceived little knowledge of developmental milestones noted that they do
not expect direct eye contact and that past early childhood it becomes judged
as disrespectful with peers and adults (Grinker et
al., 2012). Perhaps the emphasis on eye contact stems from Westerners’ (mis)perception of co-interactants
or onlookers, as they may feel rejected or devalued by someone who averts their
eye gaze (Wirth et al., 2010), contributing to the alienation of some autistic
people.
Furthermore,
raters may observe that autistic people’s reduced or atypical eye contact may
not indicate social disinterest in or disengagement. It may reflect a coping
mechanism for feeling overwhelmed from eye-to-eye contact due to difficulties
with visual overload (Gernsbacher et al., 2008), listening and watching
simultaneously (Doherty-Sneddon et al., 2012; Falck-Ytter,
2015), or processing complex movement (Elsabbagh et
al., 2012; Hanley et al., 2013; Weisberg et al., 2012). Similarly, autistic
individuals may avert eye contact when perceiving others’ expressions as
threatening (without necessarily pervasive social anxiety: (Gernsbacher and Frymiare, 2005; Tottenham et al.,
2014). Autistic people’s eye contact may lack typical social flexibility for
reasons including domain-general (i.e., not limited to social contexts) poor
oculomotor (eye movement) control (Kirchgessner et
al., 2015) or atypically sustained (or ‘sticky’) visual attention (Keehn et al., 2013; Sacrey et
al., 2014), and ‘freezing’ gaze toward facial expressions perceived as
threatening in a manner atypical even for non-autistic socially anxious people
(White et al., 2015).
In
contrast, the restricted and repetitive behaviours
and interests domain of autism measures may provide more meaningful information
than interactive behaviours that inherently vary by
social context. Sensory and motor behaviours may
underlie the autism ‘symptoms’ and items of repetitive motor movements and
sensory interests, while hyperfocused attention may
contribute to perseverative interests or behaviours.
Despite the heterogeneity of autism, sensory, motor, and general attentional
differences (as measured by ADOS and other instruments) consistently emerge as
its earliest manifestations in empirical research such as longitudinal studies
of infant siblings of autistic children (Gallagher and Varga,
2015; Gliga et al., 2014; Rogers, 2009; Sacrey et al., 2015). Similarly, studies using various
autism instruments report that repetitive behaviours
show relative stability while atypical social behaviours
reduced more quickly across different developmental trajectories in autistic
toddlers through adults with various intellectual and language abilities (Fecteau et al., 2003; Fountain et al., 2012; Pellicano,
2012; Piven et al., 1996; Seltzer et al., 2003; Soke et al., 2011). Additional evidence for these general
(not socially specific) mechanisms as driving autism stems from the only (to my
knowledge) longitudinal study from toddlerhood to adulthood to claim some
individuals outgrow autism according to standardised
instruments, which reported that a reduction in repetitive behaviours
between ages two and three predicted no longer meeting criteria on the ADOS by
age 19 (Anderson et al., 2014).
The
apparent importance of these general features of autism despite their small
proportion of autism’s diagnostic criteria and affiliated instruments suggest
meaningful patterns. Nevertheless, I tended to ‘under-score’ sensory and motor
symptoms and ‘over-score’ communication symptoms relative to the group. This
dichotomy may both highlight the difficulty of evaluating domain-general behaviours in social contexts and perhaps my indoctrination
into the socially and medically biased autism field.
Reliability: Looking through the
Kaleidoscope of Autism through a Forced Lens
Although
one could endlessly debate the validity of the particular diagnostic tools or
indeed the autism construct itself, the assessment
tool arguably enables the achievement of reliability, perhaps because of its
basis on elicited behaviours in particular contexts.
Despite differences in criteria used to determine and allocation of Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-IV) diagnoses within the autism
spectrum by North American university-based clinical sites, the centres shared similar distributions of scores on standardised assessment measures, especially the (social
communication scores of) ADOS (Lord et al., 2012). The only study to my
knowledge to test the interrater reliability of the ADOS more naturalistically
via routine clinical practice across multidisciplinary sites found agreement on
scores comparable to research-reliable samples (Zander et al., 2016). Another independent study reported that only
the ADOS (Module 4) could reliably identify autism among adults in the
community in England (Brugha et al., 2012). In
contrast, separate research teams have reported inconsistent results from
alternative questionnaire measures (Brugha et al.,
2012; Sizoo et al., 2015).
Making
a contrast with psychopathy further
suggests the strengths in reliability of a behaviourally
based standardised diagnostic instrument for ASD
relative to more subjective measures. Psychopathy differs from autism as a
personality disorder with a callous manipulativeness
that enables some people to exploit others through predatory social skills, and
diagnostic assessment is made using the Psychopathy Checklist – Revised (PCL-R;
(Hare, 2003). Although another interview-based tool that requires certified
training and reputedly the diagnostic ‘gold standard’ of its field, the PCL-R
fails to demonstrate inter-rater reliability
outside controlled research settings, especially for its core
psychosocial personality traits as opposed to items of impulsive behaviour or criminal history (Edens
et al., 2010). PCL-R diagnosed offenders can often generate an impression of
empathy rather than meanness within the first few seconds of an interaction
(Fowler et al., 2009; Robinson and Rogers, 2015), and those with high ability
to infer others’ thoughts or feelings may more often malinger (report false
medical symptoms or illness) to avoid harsh punishment (Nentjes
et al., 2015). Agreeable (trusting, caring, etc.) people may more often feel
convinced by these manipulative acts or give the benefit of the doubt,
therefore raters’ own personality traits influence their scoring on the PCL-R
(Miller et al., 2011). Thus while both autism and psychopathy inherently affect
social functioning, autism’s behavioural definition
and the deception practiced by psychopathic people may explain the higher
(moderate) correlations achieved between autistic youth, their parents, and
teachers in the social domain (Stratis and Lecavalier, 2015), compared with the only modest such
inter-rater agreement for adolescents with ‘fledgling’ psychopathy (Docherty et
al., 2016). The autism field’s relative agreement on definition and greater
availability of supports also lend more utility to the diagnosis.
Conclusion
Diagnostic
tools may oversimplify and pathologise autism, but as
the facilitator said, no type of assessment can be used alone and they hardly
serve as a measure of treatment outcomes. The DSM-5 Neurodevelopmental
Disorders Workgroup that revised autism’s diagnosis said criteria work best for
5-to-8-year-old white boys (Swedo et al., 2012), and
similarly (as acknowledged by the facilitator in planned presentation or
answers to questions) the instrument struggles in application to some groups
(women and girls, adults especially without fluent speech or with severe intellectual
disability; typists who do not speak; non-native speakers of English; people
with selective mutism, blindness or deafness; or physical impairments). It may
not apply to all autistic people, but perhaps it can help to identify patterns
for particular subsets. Assessments may benefit from incorporating strengths
(as scientifically supported) in the items, as these may help to suggest
support tailored to individual profiles of strengths and weaknesses. Such a
change would require a revolution in the classification of autism, one long
overdue to view individuals holistically and not as a collection of pathology.
Discussion- A summary of themes
Ginny
Russell is a social scientist and epidemiologist
Here,
I attempt to summarise the common themes raised by
the authors. In order to do so, the commentaries were coded and points where
all had raised similar topics as well as disagreements were noted. I identified three recurring themes in the
four commentaries about the diagnostic tool: one theme centred
on epistemic authority and power, whilst another raised questions over the
tool’s objectivity. All four authors discussed the commercial nature of the
course. A final theme covers differences between the commentaries. Overall the
authors described how the tool played an active role in shaping the context of
the assessment and our understanding of how we read behaviour
and ultimately what we know autism to be. For example, the fourth author notes
the “interaction-based assessment tool illuminated autism’s construction as a
disorder mostly of social communication”. The second author writes how the tool
has a role “recording autistic behaviour as
‘mechanical’ and thus reifying the much critiqued machine-like metaphor often
used to describe autistic people”. All authors also passed judgement on the
utility of the tool and diagnosis more generally, but disagreements arose here.
1. Power
relations
All
four authors commented on the power relations inherent in the training process
and the autistic authors noted especially the power gap between autistic and
non-autistic people inherent in the tool’s development and implementation. One
author described how the tool was presented as ‘factual based’, masking the
power relations between the passive subjects of the test, and clinicians or
researchers, who do the testing, and have authority in in the diagnostic
decision making process, acting as ‘gatekeepers’ of diagnosis. Those in power
were able to judge who qualified as normal or abnormal, such individuals are
bestowed the epistemic authority to diagnose and/or deny diagnosis.
Commentaries described how language on the training course was used to position
autistic behaviours as always problematic, describing
‘symptoms’ of autism. Whereas the
commentators (who were themselves part of the autism community) sometimes
viewed behaviour in a different, more positive light:
I
saw the child regularly smiling, but the facilitator said this was not smiling
but ‘smirking’
We
laugh with recognition and delight in the fun the boy is having. He is not reliant on approval from the
diagnostician, and we appreciate his exuberance and his ability to see things
differently.
The
process involved learning to record children’s behaviour
in standardised, replicable, objective, quantifiable,
mechanistic and measurable ways, as ‘a collection of pathology’. Thus the
course trained students to interpret children’s behaviour
through a lens of autism, reminiscent of the Foucauldian medical gaze (1973).
In this way, diagnostic tools themselves might promote the construction of
autism through a deficit-based diagnostic narrative (through training
participants to recognise certain ways of
interpreting autistic behaviour):
Autistic
ways of being are described as “compensatory strategies”. Interests are described
as “obsessions”, “fixated” and abnormal for not being able to “shift flexibly
around the interests and behaviour of the
administrator”, whilst the reverse is seen as unproblematic.
Our
authors commented on the influence of context in assessment and the power of
the training to promote reading of children’s behaviour
as autistic symptoms. Such reading in the light of a diagnosis is suggestive of
writings of labelling theorists of the 1970s, for example Rosenhan’s
‘On being sane in insane places’ (1973): once incarcerated for schizophrenia, Rosenhan and his (sane) colleagues had their behaviours routinely interpreted as manifestations of
schizophrenia by health professionals.
The
emotional responses of the commentators who found the film clips of children
‘distressing’ and affecting were not brought to the fore during the course. It
is not clear if the emotional effect of the training on practitioners and
subjects is discussed in detail as a routine part of training to use the
diagnostic tool. There was an overall impression of unease in all the
commentaries concerning informed consent and around whether children were
benefitting from and enjoying the assessment process, contributing to a further
sense of imbalance of power.
2. Objectivity,
subjectivity and context
Although
the tool was presented as a way to standardise,
quantify and measure behaviours reliably and
objectively, questions over a lack of objectivity emerged as a recurring theme.
Although one author commented on the extensive research evidence that shows
reliability of this tool, all authors discussed instances where contextual
factors might undermine the replicability of children’s behaviour.
These included examiners’ behaviour and how this
might impact on the child, the unfamiliar setting and person, age, gender and
wider cultural context that might establish which behaviours
are deemed especially problematic. An example was direct eye gaze which in
South Africa is ‘judged as disrespectful with peers and adults’ (whereas on the
course lack of gaze was taught to be interpreted as deficient). This was seen
as an instance of culturally determined values being represented as children’s
deficits.
The
language of the course also served to present the rating process as ‘standardised’, ‘valid’, ‘reliable’ and ‘objective’. Thus
the visceral and emotional nature of a child’s behaviour
and interaction with the rater was (perhaps necessarily) reduced to a set of
data. A final score was calculated: ultimately this was reducible again to a
yes/no binary – does the child have autism or not?
The
course trained its participants to interpret social and communicative behaviours as a facet of the individual person: an inherent
quality or trait of the individual. All the authors made the point that social
skills only exist in relation to others, e.g. “Robinson Crusoe couldn’t have
been autistic until he found Man Friday”.
The commentaries called for transparency over the constructed
relationship between the examiner and the child, and the setting and nature of
the test, which might provoke certain types of behaviour.
These
looked more like tests of social conformity to a bossy adult’s constantly
shifting demands.
Thus,
in a similar way to Turowetz and Maynard (2015, 2017)
the commentaries drew out how the nature of the test itself (“a contrived
social situation”) could influence the diagnostic outcome. Two authors in
particular took umbrage with the tool’s assessing and identifying autism
primarily through deficits in social skills and communication. One placed more
emphasis instead on sensory differences: suggesting the tool should be reformed
with more emphasis on sensory sensitivity, rather than social behaviour. Such arguments drew attention to how the tool
itself plays an active role: in this
case constructing what we understand autism to be: primarily a condition of
social problems. This was a point of critique ‘it attempts to identify
relational ‘deficit’ whilst demonstrating the instrument’s own lack of
awareness about the nature of relationships’.
3. Commercialisation and lack of transparency
A
final aspect of the tool that all authors drew attention to was the status of
the tool as “a commercial product”. The training and tool employed a business
model involving upselling of various other related products. This raised the
question of in whose interests was it to promote the tool, and promote
diagnosis and identification of autism more generally. The commercialisation
of autism into the ‘autism industry’, an enterprise designed to engender
commercial gain, was not explicitly described as objectionable. The authors
gave the impression that what was objectionable was actually the lack of
transparency about this commercial aim of the tool, and its pretension of
objectivity without much succour to its own limitations.
One author noted the “whole process should come out from behind the wall of
professional and commercial exclusivity”. However, this raises the question of
whether the commercial nature of the tool could conflict with the need for
clarity about limitations of assessment. In other words, if the training was
more open and involved more reflection regarding of the role of context,
constructed relationships and the training itself as a mechanism to read behaviour through an autism-as-deficit diagnostic lens,
would this undermine raters’ faith in this particular tool? And could that lead
to less use (and sales)? Would more transparency in training about limitations
of the tool destabilize the commercial enterprise?
I
would argue this is not necessarily the case as most clinicians and researchers
are able to understand that tools they use are imperfect and take a pragmatic
view. The ethnographers and medical sociologists have shown how doctors are
taught to rely on their own knowledge as a source of certainty (Atkinson 1995).
Latimer (2013) shows how clinicians will ignore a diagnostic test if it
conflicts with their own medical judgement. Rather, Latimer shows, test results
for genetic conditions are woven in with other sources of evidence such as
family history, patient testimony and impact on functioning to create a
diagnostic story or narrative about the patient’s predicament. Social factors
(like local access to specialist schooling) may further influence diagnostic
decision-making in autism clinics.
Hedgecoe
(2004) has written about how medical authority rests on the claim that
clinicians are ‘certain’ about a diagnosis. Diagnostic tools such as ADOS are
presented as factual, reliable and objective. But what of the
commercialisation of the training and use of the
diagnostic tool? Hedgecoe talks about how acknowledging uncertainty in
assessment might undermine the medical and commercial endeavours
of establishing authority. What, he asks, does it do to professional status of
the rater if their tools are shot through with uncertainty?
4. Where
authors did not agree
There
was divergence about the overall utility of the tool, and validity of autism as
a concept. One author who was autistic himself, so had invested in autism as a
concept, argued for reform and modification of the tool. Another author took a
more revolutionary stance dismissing the entire tool as a “diagnostic trap”,
with a wholesale rejection of the concept of autism. Along similar lines, the
authors had differing assessments of the utility of the tool. Whilst all
provided a critical commentary, two authors ultimately made arguments for the
utility and necessity of assessment: ‘obtaining a diagnosis might help the
boy’. This was because of the crucial gatekeeping function of diagnosis in
releasing resources, allowing others to adjust their expectations, aligning
researchers to a common understanding, and the way an autism diagnosis could
allow access to a supportive community of autistic others. Without the
diagnosis, the parent activist wondered “will he be viewed merely as wilfully uncooperative and hence condemned to exclusion
without support?” According to this account, although the tool was flawed,
identification and diagnosis was necessary: somebody has to judge, somebody has
to have authority: as “self-identification will never be a viable way forward”,
and “I still feel there is an important utility in the umbrella category of
autism spectrum disorder”. In contrast
the first author questioned the basic assumption that “ASD exists as a
discrete, natural ‘thing’, and ‘that this autism ‘thing’ can be identified and
quantified”.
Although
all were critically appraising the tool (as requested), none of the authors
gave much thought to an alternative system that might replace the functions of
diagnosis. But this was not in their brief. The current diagnostic system has
been heavily critiqued from both psychiatry and outside but diagnosis serves
many valuable functions in our society (Rose, 2013). Nevertheless, attempts
have been made to forge alternative systems of classification. For example, the
Power Threat Meaning Framework (Johnstone et al, 2018) is a UK-based attempt
led by clinical psychologists and service users to drop the diagnosis of mental
health conditions, although this has come under fire from social scientists and
psychiatry. The International Classification of Functioning (ICF) presents an
alternative taxonomy to the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders (DSM) and International Classification of Diseases (ICD), using
ability as well as disability to classify individuals into types.
Medical
sociologists (Jutel and Nettleton 2011) have
discussed how medical nosology, through application as diagnosis, promotes and
maintains a certain medical reality. Authors differed as to whether using the
diagnostic tool was ultimately a worthwhile and necessary endeavour.
If we accept we need a category of autism (and not all the authors did) then
surely it becomes necessary to standardise and measure
autism in ways researchers and clinicians (tool users) recognise
and agree on. A repeated critique from the autistic authors,
though was the lack of autistic input in the tool’s development. The question
of who decides how autism is defined is clearly political as well as
evidence-based. Diagnostic tools may be the best way of identifying autism at
the present time, but authors drew attention to their active role in
constructing what autism is understood to be. In this sense the understanding
of autism we currently work with is whatever it is the gold standard tool
measures.
Despite
some fairly fundamental disagreements, all critiqued the tool’s lack of
transparency, recognizing context, emotion, and differences in interpretation
and power imbalances as playing an unidentified role in the assessment process.
Based on these analyses, we recommend that training for raters for such tools
should be accessible to a wider group of people, and incorporate more explicit
recognition of its own limitations.
References
Akhtar, Nameera, and Morton Ann
Gernsbacher. 2008. On Privileging the Role of Gaze in Infant Social Cognition. Child Development Perspectives. 2(2): 59–65.
Anderson,
Deborah K., Jessie W. Liang, and Catherine Lord. 2014. Predicting Young Adult
Outcome among More and Less Cognitively Able Individuals with Autism Spectrum
Disorders. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry.
55(5): 485–494.
Atkinson,
Paul. 1995. Medical Talk and Medical Work: The Liturgy of the Clinic. 1 edition. London: Sage Publications UK..
Bird, Geoffrey, Jane Leighton, Clare Press, and Cecilia Heyes. 2007. Intact Automatic Imitation of Human and Robot Actions
in Autism Spectrum Disorders. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B:
Biological Sciences. 274(1628): 3027–3031.
Brugha, T. S., S. McManus, J. Smith, et al. 2012. Validating Two Survey Methods for Identifying Cases of Autism
Spectrum Disorder among Adults in the Community. Psychological
Medicine. 42(3): 647–656.
Cage, Eilidh, Elizabeth Pellicano, Punit Shah, and Geoffrey Bird. 2013. Reputation
Management: Evidence for Ability But Reduced
Propensity in Autism. Autism Research. 6(5): 433–442.
Chapman,
Robert. 2016. Autism Isn’t Just A Medical Diagnosis —
It’s A Political Identity. The Establishment.
https://theestablishment.co/autism-isnt-just-a-medical-diagnosis-it-s-a-political-identity-178137688bd5,
accessed July 17, 2017.
Chapman,
Robert. 2017. Autism and Intersectional Theory. Paper presented at the Autism
and Society Seminar II: Autistic Wellbeing, UCL Institute of Education, London,
March 1.
Chown,
Nicholas. 2014. More on the Ontological Status of Autism and Double Empathy. Disability & Society. 29(10): 1672–1676.
Chown,
Nicholas Paul. 2013. The Mismeasure of Autism: A
Challenge to Orthodox Autism Theory. Autonomy, the Critical Journal of
Interdisciplinary Autism Studies 1(2).
http://www.larry-arnold.net/Autonomy/index.php/autonomy/article/view/AR5,
accessed July 17, 2017.
Cottenceau, Hélène, Sylvie Roux, Romuald
Blanc, et al. 2012. Quality of Life of Adolescents with Autism Spectrum
Disorders: Comparison to Adolescents with Diabetes. European
Child & Adolescent Psychiatry. 21(5): 289–296.
Dawson,
Michelle. 2012. CRAE LectureInstitute of Education,
London, March 1.
Dekker,
Martijn. 2016. Cure versus Acceptance: A False Dichotomy? Paper presented at
the Autism-Europe Conference, Edinburgh, September 16.
Docherty, Meagan, Paul Boxer, L. Rowell Huesmann,
Maureen O’Brien, and Brad J. Bushman. 2016. Exploring Primary and
Secondary Variants of Psychopathy in Adolescents in Detention and in the
Community. Journal of Clinical Child & Adolescent
Psychology. 45(5): 564–578.
Doherty-Sneddon,
Gwyneth, Deborah M. Riby, and Lisa Whittle. 2012.
Gaze Aversion as a Cognitive Load Management Strategy in Autism Spectrum
Disorder and Williams Syndrome. Journal of Child Psychology
and Psychiatry. 53(4): 420–430.
Dreaper, Jane. 2017. Autism Diagnoses “Could Be Reduced under NHS
Plan.” BBC News, May 27.
http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/health-40058482, accessed July 17, 2017.
Edens, John
F., Marcus T. Boccaccini, and Darryl W. Johnson. 2010. Inter-Rater
Reliability of the PCL-R Total and Factor Scores among Psychopathic Sex
Offenders: Are Personality Features More Prone to Disagreement than Behavioral
Features? Behavioral Sciences & the Law. 28(1):
106–119.
Elsabbagh, Mayada, Evelyne Mercure,
Kristelle Hudry, et al. 2012. Infant Neural
Sensitivity to Dynamic Eye Gaze Is Associated with Later Emerging Autism. Current Biology. 22(4): 338–342.
Falck-Ytter, Terje. 2015. Gaze Performance during Face-to-Face Communication: A
Live Eye Tracking Study of Typical Children and Children with Autism. Research in Autism Spectrum Disorders. 17: 78–85.
Fecteau,
Shirley, Laurent Mottron, Claude Berthiaume, and
Jacob A. Burack. 2003. Developmental Changes of
Autistic Symptoms. Autism. 7(3): 255–268.
Feldman, Ruth, Ofer Golan, Yael Hirschler-Guttenberg, Sharon Ostfeld-Etzion,
and Orna Zagoory-Sharon. 2014. Parent-Child Interaction
and Oxytocin Production in Pre-Schoolers with Autism Spectrum Disorder. The British Journal of Psychiatry. 205(2): 107–112.
Fleming,
Bernard, Elizabeth Hurley, and The Goth. 2016. Choosing Autism Interventions: A Research-Based Guide.
United Kingdom: Pavilion Publishing and Media Ltd.
Foucault,
Michel. 1973. The Birth of the Clinic. trans. A.
Sheridan, London: Tavistock.
Fountain, Christine, Alix S.
Winter, and Peter S. Bearman. 2012. Six Developmental
Trajectories Characterize Children With Autism. Pediatrics.
129(5): e1112–e1120.
Fowler, Katherine A., Scott O. Lilienfeld,
and Christopher J. Patrick. 2009. Detecting Psychopathy from Thin Slices of
Behavior. Psychological Assessment 21(1): 68–78.
Gallagher, Shaun, and Somogy Varga. 2015. Conceptual Issues in Autism Spectrum Disorders. Current Opinion in Psychiatry. 28(2): 127–132.
Gernsbacher, Morton Ann, and Jennifer L. Frymiare. 2005. Does the Autistic
Brain Lack Core Modules? The Journal of Developmental and
Learning Disorders. 9: 3–16.
Gernsbacher, Morton Ann, Jennifer L. Stevenson, and Sebastian
Dern.
2017. Specificity, Contexts, and Reference Groups Matter When Assessing
Autistic Traits. PLOS ONE. 12(2): e0171931.
Gernsbacher, Morton Ann, Jennifer L. Stevenson, Suraiya Khandakar, and H. Hill
Goldsmith. 2008. Why Does Joint Attention Look Atypical in Autism? Child Development Perspectives. 2(1): 38–45.
Gliga, T., E.
J. H. Jones, R. Bedford, T. Charman, and M. H.
Johnson. 2014. From Early Markers to Neuro-Developmental
Mechanisms of Autism. Developmental Review. 34(3):
189–207.
Grandin,
Temple. 2006. Thinking in Pictures, Expanded Edition: My Life with Autism. Vintage.
Grinker, Roy Richard, Nola Chambers, Nono Njongwe, et al. 2012. “Communities” in Community
Engagement: Lessons Learned From Autism Research in South Korea and South
Africa. Autism Research. 5(3): 201–210.
Hanley, Mary, Martin McPhillips, Gerry Mulhern,
and Deborah M Riby. 2013. Spontaneous Attention to Faces
in Asperger Syndrome Using Ecologically Valid Static Stimuli. Autism. 17(6): 754–761.
Happé,
Francesca, and Angelica Ronald. 2008. The ‘Fractionable
Autism Triad’: A Review of Evidence from Behavioural,
Genetic, Cognitive and Neural Research. Neuropsychology
Review. 18(4): 287–304.
Haraway, Donna. 1988. Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in
Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective. Feminist Studies. 14(3):
575–599.
Hare, R D. 2003. The Psychopathy Checklist – Revised,
2nd Edition. Toronto, ON: Multi-Health Systems, Inc.
Hayes, Jennie, Tamsin Ford, Hateem Rafeeque, and Ginny Russell. 2018. Clinical Practice Guidelines
for Diagnosis of Autism Spectrum Disorder in Adults and Children in the UK: A
Narrative Review. BMC Psychiatry. 18(1): 222.
Hedgecoe,
Adam. 2004. The Politics of Personalised Medicine:
Pharmacogenetics in the Clinic. New York: Cambridge University Press..
Izuma, Keise, Kenji Matsumoto, Colin F. Camerer,
and Ralph Adolphs. 2011. Insensitivity to Social
Reputation in Autism. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences. 108(42): 17302–17307.
Jenkins, Tania M., and Susan E. Short. 2017. Negotiating
Intersex: A Case for Revising the Theory of Social Diagnosis. Social Science & Medicine (1982) 175: 91–98.
Jutel, Annemarie. 2011. Putting a Name to It: Diagnosis in
Contemporary Society. JHU Press.
Jutel,
Annemarie, and Sarah Nettleton. 2011. “Towards a Sociology
of Diagnosis: Reflections and Opportunities.” Social Science & Medicine
(1982) 73 (6): 793–800. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.socscimed.2011.07.014..
Kapp, Steven K., Kristen Gillespie-Lynch, Lauren E. Sherman,
and Ted Hutman. 2013. Deficit, Difference, or Both? Autism and Neurodiversity. Developmental
Psychology. 49(1): 59–71.
Keehn,
Brandon, Ralph-Axel Müller, and Jeanne Townsend. 2013. Atypical Attentional Networks
and the Emergence of Autism. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral
Reviews 37(2): 164–183.
Kenny,
Lorcan, Caroline Hattersley, Bonnie Molins, et al. 2015. Which Terms Should Be Used to Describe
Autism? Perspectives from the UK Autism Community. Autism.
Kirchgessner, Megan
A., Alice Z. Chuang, Saumil S. Patel, and Anne B. Sereno. 2015. Intact Reflexive but Deficient Voluntary Social
Orienting in Autism Spectrum Disorder. Frontiers in
Neuroscience 9. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4665260/.
Lawson,
Wendy. 2008. Concepts of Normality: The Autistic and Typical Spectrum. Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
Lawson,
Wendy. 2010 The Passionate Mind: How People with Autism Learn. Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
Latimer,
Joanna. 2013. The Gene, the Clinic, and the Family: Diagnosing Dysmorphology, Reviving Medical Dominance. Routledge.
Lord,
C., M. Rutter, and A. Couteur. 1994. Autism
Diagnostic Interview-Revised: A Revised Version of a Diagnostic Interview for
Caregivers of Individuals with Possible Pervasive Developmental Disorders. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders. 24(5):
659–685.
Lord,
Catherine, Eva Petkova, Vanessa Hus, et al. 2012. A Multisite Study of the Clinical Diagnosis of Different Autism
Spectrum Disorders. Archives of General Psychiatry 69(3): 306–313.
Maynard, Douglas W., and Jason J. Turowetz. 2017. Doing Testing: How
Concrete Competence Can Facilitate or Inhibit Performances of Children with
Autism Spectrum Disorder. Qualitative Sociology 40(4): 467–491.
Miller, Audrey K., Katrina A. Rufino,
Marcus T. Boccaccini, Rebecca L. Jackson, and Daniel
C. Murrie. 2011. On Individual Differences in
Person Perception: Raters’ Personality Traits Relate to Their Psychopathy
Checklist-Revised Scoring Tendencies. Assessment 18(2): 253–260.
Milton,
Damian E. M. 2012. On the Ontological Status of Autism: The ‘Double Empathy
Problem.’ Disability & Society 27(6): 883–887.
Milton,
Damian E. M. 2014. Autistic Expertise: A Critical Reflection on the Production
of Knowledge in Autism Studies. Autism 18(7): 794–802.
Mostofsky,
Stewart H., and Joshua B. Ewen. 2011. Altered
Connectivity and Action Model Formation in Autism Is Autism. The Neuroscientist
17(4): 437–448.
Mottron, Laurent. 2017. Should We Change Targets and Methods of
Early Intervention in Autism, in Favor of a Strengths-Based Education? European
Child & Adolescent Psychiatry 26(7): 815–825.
Mottron,
Laurent, Michelle Dawson, Isabelle Soulières, Benedicte Hubert, and Jake Burack.
2006. Enhanced Perceptual Functioning in
Autism: An Update, and Eight Principles of Autistic Perception. Journal of
Autism and Developmental Disorders 36(1): 27–43.
Müller, Ralph-Axel, and David G. Amaral. 2017. Editorial: Time to Give up on Autism Spectrum Disorder? Autism Research 10(1):
10–14.
Murray, Dinah, Mike Lesser, and Wendy Lawson. 2005. Attention, Monotropism and the Diagnostic Criteria for Autism. Autism
9(2): 139–156.
Nentjes, Lieke, David P. Bernstein, Arnoud
Arntz, Mariëtte E. Slaats, and Tina Hannemann. 2015. Theory of Mind,
Social Desirability, and Unlikely Symptom Reporting in Offenders With and
Without Psychopathy. Journal of Nervous & Mental Disease 203(8): 596–603.
Norbury,
Courtenay Frazier, Helen Griffiths, and Kate Nation. 2010. Sound before
Meaning: Word Learning in Autistic Disorders. Neuropsychologia
48(14): 4012–4019.
Ortega,
Francisco. 2009. The Cerebral Subject and the Challenge of Neurodiversity. BioSocieties 4(04): 425–445.
Parma, Valentina, Maria Bulgheroni,
Roberto Tirindelli, and Umberto Castiello. 2013. Body Odors Promote
Automatic Imitation in Autism. Biological Psychiatry 74(3).
Oxytocin and Autism: 220–226.
Pellicano,
Elizabeth. 2012. Do Autistic Symptoms Persist Across Time? Evidence of
Substantial Change in Symptomatology Over a 3-Year
Period in Cognitively Able Children With Autism. American Journal on
Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities 117(2): 156–166.
Piven,
Joseph, Jennifer Harper, Pat Palmer, and Stephan Arndt. 1996. Course of
Behavioral Change in Autism: A Retrospective Study of High-IQ Adolescents and
Adults. Journal of the American Academy of Child & Adolescent Psychiatry
35(4): 523–529.
Prainsack,
Barbara, and Alena Buyx. 2011. Solidarity:
Reflections on an Emerging Concept in Bioethics. Nuffield
Council on Bioethics.
Robinson, Emily V., and Richard Rogers. 2015. Empathy Faking in
Psychopathic Offenders: The Vulnerability of Empathy Measures. Journal of
Psychopathology and Behavioral Assessment 37(4): 545–552.
Rogers,
Sally J. 2009. What Are Infant Siblings Teaching Us about Autism in Infancy? Autism Research. 2(3): 125–137.
Rose,
Nikolas. 2013. What Is Diagnosis For? Royal College of Psychiatry: Conference
on DSM-5 and the Future of Diagnosis.
Rosenhan, D L. 1973. “On Being Sane in Insane Places.”
Science (New York, N.Y.) 179 (70): 250–58. https://doi.org/4683124..
Sacrey,
Lori-Ann R., Vickie L. Armstrong, Susan E. Bryson, and Lonnie Zwaigenbaum. 2014. Impairments to Visual
Disengagement in Autism Spectrum Disorder: A Review of Experimental Studies
from Infancy to Adulthood. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral
Reviews 47: 559–577.
Sacrey,
Lori-Ann R., Jeffrey A. Bennett, and Lonnie Zwaigenbaum. 2015. Early Infant
Development and Intervention for Autism Spectrum Disorder. Journal of Child
Neurology 30(14): 1921–1929.
Sasson, Noah J., Daniel J. Faso, Jack Nugent, et al. 2017. Neurotypical Peers Are Less Willing to Interact with Those
with Autism Based on Thin Slice Judgments. Scientific Reports
7. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5286449/.
Satel, Sally,
and Scott O. Lilienfeld. 2013. Brainwashed: The
Seductive Appeal of Mindless Neuroscience. New York: Basic Civitas
Books.
Seltzer, Marsha Mailick, Marty Wyngaarden Krauss, Paul T. Shattuck, et al. 2003. The
Symptoms of Autism Spectrum Disorders in Adolescence and Adulthood.
Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 33(6): 565–581.
Sheppard, Elizabeth, Dhanya Pillai,
Genevieve Tze-Lynn Wong, Danielle Ropar, and Peter
Mitchell. 2016. How Easy Is It to Read the Minds of People with Autism Spectrum
Disorder? Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 46(4): 1247–1254.
Sinclair,
Jim. 2012. Don’t Mourn for Us. Autonomy, the Critical Journal of
Interdisciplinary Autism Studies 1(1).
http://www.larry-arnold.net/Autonomy/index.php/autonomy/article/view/AR1,
accessed July 17, 2017.
Sizoo, Bram
B, EH Horwitz, JP Teunisse, et al. 2015. Predictive
Validity of Self-Report Questionnaires in the Assessment of Autism Spectrum
Disorders in Adults. Autism 19(7): 842–849.
Soke, Gnakub Norbert, Amy Philofsky,
Carolyn Diguiseppi, et al. 2011. Longitudinal Changes in
Scores on the Autism Diagnostic Interview—Revised (ADI-R) in Pre-School
Children with Autism: Implications for Diagnostic Classification and Symptom
Stability. Autism 15(5): 545–562.
Solomon, O. 2011. Rethinking Baby
Talk. In: The Handbook of Language Socialization Pp. 121–149. Chichester, UK: Willey-Blackwell.
Sowden, Sophie, Svenja Koehne, Caroline Catmur, Isabel Dziobek, and Geoffrey Bird. 2016. Intact Automatic Imitation and
Typical Spatial Compatibility in Autism Spectrum Disorder: Challenging the
Broken Mirror Theory. Autism Research 9(2): 292–300.
Spengler, Stephanie, Geoffrey Bird, and Marcel Brass. 2010. Hyperimitation
of Actions Is Related to Reduced Understanding of
Others’ Minds in Autism Spectrum Conditions. Biological
Psychiatry. 68(12). Cortical Development and
Cognitive Function: 1148–1155.
Starr,
Sandy. 2009. Conversations with the Author (Personal Communication).
Stratis,
Elizabeth A., and Luc Lecavalier. 2015. Informant Agreement for Youth with
Autism Spectrum Disorder or Intellectual Disability: A Meta-Analysis. Journal
of Autism and Developmental Disorders 45(4): 1026–1041.
Swedo, Susan E., Gillian Baird, Edwin H. Cook, et al. 2012. Commentary from the DSM-5 Workgroup on Neurodevelopmental
Disorders. Journal of the American Academy of Child & Adolescent
Psychiatry 51(4): 347–349.
Timimi, Sami, Niel Gardner, and Bain McCabe. 2011. The Myth of Autism.
UK: Palgrave-MacMillan.
Tottenham, Nim, Margaret E. Hertzig, Kristen Gillespie-Lynch, et al. 2014 . Elevated Amygdala
Response to Faces and Gaze Aversion in Autism Spectrum Disorder. Social
Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 9(1): 106–117.
Turowetz, Jason. 2015. The Interactional Production of a Clinical
Fact in a Case of Autism. Qualitative Sociology 38(1): 57–78.
Verhoeff, Berend. 2012. What Is This Thing
Called Autism? A Critical Analysis of the Tenacious Search for Autism’s
Essence. BioSocieties 7(4): 410–432.
Walsh,
Pat. 2010. Asperger Syndrome and the Supposed Obligation Not
to Bring Disabled Lives into the World. Journal of Medical Ethics:
jme.2010.036459.
Weisberg, Jill, Shawn C. Milleville,
Lauren Kenworthy, et al. 2012. Social Perception in
Autism Spectrum Disorders: Impaired Category Selectivity for Dynamic but Not
Static Images in Ventral Temporal Cortex. Cerebral Cortex 24(1): 37–48.
White,
Susan W., Brenna B. Maddox, and Robin K. Panneton.
2015. Fear of Negative Evaluation Influences Eye Gaze in Adolescents with
Autism Spectrum Disorder: A Pilot Study. Journal of Autism and Developmental
Disorders 45(11): 3446–3457.
Wing, Lorna, Susan R. Leekam, Sarah
J. Libby, Judith Gould, and Michael Larcombe. 2002. The Diagnostic
Interview for Social and Communication Disorders: Background, Inter-Rater
Reliability and Clinical Use. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 43(3):
307–325.
Wirth, James H., Donald F. Sacco, Kurt Hugenberg,
and Kipling D. Williams. 2010. Eye Gaze as Relational Evaluation: Averted Eye Gaze
Leads to Feelings of Ostracism and Relational Devaluation. Personality and
Social Psychology Bulletin 36(7): 869–882.
Wittemeyer, K., A.
English, G. Jones, L. Lyn-Cook, and D. Milton. 2012. Schools Autism Competency
Framework. London: AET.
Zander, Eric, Charlotte Willfors,
Steve Berggren, et al. 2016. The Objectivity of the Autism
Diagnostic Observation Schedule (ADOS) in Naturalistic Clinical Settings.
European Child & Adolescent Psychiatry 25(7): 769–780.